Why Do We Care For The Bodies Of The Dead?
The ancient Greek Cynic philosopher Diogenes was extreme in
a lot of ways. He deliberately lived on the street, and, in accordance with his
teachings that people should not be embarrassed to do private things in public,
was said to defecate and masturbate openly in front of others. Plato called him
“a Socrates gone mad.” Shocking right to the end, he told his friends that when
he died, he didn’t want to be buried. He wanted them to throw his body over the
city wall, where it could be devoured by animals.
“What harm then can the mangling of wild beasts do me if I
am without consciousness?” he asked.
What is a dead body but an empty shell?, he’s asking. What
does it matter what happens to it? These are also the questions that the
University of California, Berkeley, history professor Thomas Laqueur asks in
his new book The Work of the Dead: A
Cultural History of Mortal Remains.
“Diogenes was right,” he writes, “but also existentially
wrong.”
This is the tension surrounding how humans treat dead
bodies. What makes a person a person is gone from their bodies upon death, and
there’s really no logical reason why we should care for the empty container—why
we should embalm it, dress it up, and put it on display, or why we should
collect its burnt remnants in an urn and place it on the mantle.
Humanity’s answer to Diogenes, Laqueur writes, has largely
been “Yes, but…” People have cared for the bodies of their dead since at least
10,000 B.C., Laqueur writes, and so the reason for continuing to do so is a
tautology: “We live with the dead because we, as a species, live with the dead.”
And the fact that we do so, he argues, is one of the things that brings us as a
species from nature into culture. (The taboo against incest is another
example.)
Despite the rationality of Diogenes’s logic, it’s
unthinkable that we would just throw the corpses of our loved ones over a wall
and leave them to the elements. Dead bodies matter because humans have decided
that they matter, and they’ve continued to matter over time even as the ways
people care for bodies have changed.
Laqueur’s book makes this argument with a dense, detailed
sketch of a relatively small slice of time and space: Western Europe from the
18th to 20th centuries. The story begins with churchyards, which “held a near
monopoly on burial throughout Christendom … for more than a thousand years,
from the Middle Ages to the early 19th century and beyond in some places.”
People would be buried (and generally had a legal right to be buried) in the
yard of the church of the parish where they lived (or in the church itself if
they were wealthy or clergy). This was a messy business. The yards were
constantly being churned up as new bodies were buried, and they got lumpy.
There weren’t many grave markers, and if there were, they were likely to read
“here lies the body,” not a particularly personal epitaph.
“The churchyard was and looked to be a place for remembering
a bounded community of the dead who belonged there,” Laquer writes, “rather
than a place for individual commemoration and mourning.”
Though bodies were jumbled together in churchyards in a way
that it made it almost impossible to find any one individual, there was some
method to their arrangement: They were buried very deliberately along an
east-west axis to line up with Jerusalem to the east, the direction from which
the resurrection was expected to come. John Calvin, the Protestant theologian,
thought the very act of burial showed faith in a corporeal resurrection.
In the early 19th century, the dominance of churchyards
began to wane, for a number of reasons. They were crowded, for one. Rotting
bodies piled up in churchyards and church vaults also produced the kind of odor
you might expect, and activists began to argue that they were unsanitary. But
Laqueur points out that churchyards had always been crowded and smelly, and
“for centuries the smell … was tolerable.” The rise of cemeteries as an
alternative to churchyards, Laqueur writes, was really part of a massive
cultural shift, one that owed a lot to the industrial revolution and the
Protestant reformation.
During and after the industrial revolution, unpleasant
things of all kinds were being removed from people’s sight. Butchers and
slaughterhouses delivered meat while keeping the blood behind the curtain;
London constructed a massive sewer system, getting people’s waste off the streets
and out of the River Thames. With this as the backdrop, it stands to reason
that people might want the dead bodies out of their cities as well—while they
didn’t pose a real public-health threat, people successfully argued that they
did, and that was enough.
The first great cemetery of the West was Père-Lachaise in
Paris, built by Napoleon, and it inspired the building of others in Copenhagen,
Glasgow, and Boston, among other cities. Unlike churchyards, these cemeteries
were stand-alone places for the dead, open to the public and largely separated
from the crowded areas of cities.
They were also disassociated from religion. “To some degree
this is about the rise of negative liberty: the right to a grave in a neutral
civic space irrespective of one’s beliefs or lack of beliefs, and the right to
a choice in rituals of burial,” Laqueur writes. The waning dominance of the
Catholic Church had a lot to do with that. Burying bodies right by the church
would remind people on their way in to pray for the dead as a way of helping
those souls stuck in purgatory. But many Protestant reformers rejected the idea
of purgatory, and argued that the dead did not need the prayers of the living.
The focus of cemeteries was not, as it had been in
churchyards, on a community of faithful dead, but on remembering the
individual. It allowed for families to be buried together, which hadn’t really
been possible in the tangle of the churchyard.
“It was a place of sentiment loosely connected, at best,
with Christian piety and intimately bound up with the emotional economics of
family,” Laqueur writes. “In it, a newly configured idolatry of the dead served
the interests less of the old God of religion than of the new gods of memory
and history: secular gods.” Cemeteries allowed for gravestones, monuments,
epitaphs, the carving of names in stone. This provides a little insurance
against the fear of death—that one’s name, at least, will outlast them. Carving
in stone is a powerful metaphor for permanence, even if it’s just wishful
thinking.
The advent of cremation as a popular practice took some of
this enchantment away from the dead body. But while in some ways people who
opted for cremation were finally recognizing the body as a shell, just like
Diogenes said, deference towards bodies was often just replaced by deference to
their ashes. Ashes are scattered, interred, and revered in many ways, just as
bodies are. And cremation has obviously not completely replaced burial by any
stretch.
If care for the dead is one of the quintessential things
about being human, fear of death is another. Being the only animal with
constant awareness of its own mortality has significant effects on how humans
behave. Often, according to terror-management theory, the thought of death will
lead people to seek out and to value more highly things that they think will
bring them immortality, in the metaphoric sense. Living on in the memories of
others would do the trick, even though we must on some level know is only a
reprieve against eventually being forgotten.
On this matter, Laqueur turns to the 17th-century poet John
Weever:
Every man, Weever writes, “desires a perpetuity after his
death.” Without this idea “man could never have awakened in him the desire to
live in the remembrance of his fellows.” And without it, human life in the
shadow of death would be unbearable and unrecognizable: “the social affections
could not have unfolded themselves un-countenanced by the faith that Man is an
immortal being.” Our love for one another differs from the love animals might
feel for one another in that an animal perishes in the field without
“anticipating the sorrow with which is associates will bemoan his death,”
whereas we “wish to be remembered by our friends.” Naming the dead, like care
for their bodies, is seen as a way to keep them among the living. And maybe it
is a way around Diogenes.
So yes, Diogenes, the body is technically nothing once void
of its soul, or consciousness, or however one conceives of the essence of a
person. We get it. But it’s a physical emblem of that person, and in caring for
it, we offer the person’s memory a chance to linger, as we hope our own will.
Even if physical death is quick and final, social death
takes time. And through communal effort, people offer each other the chance for
their names to last a little longer on Earth than their bodies do. “There is
also another way to construe the dead,” Laqueur writes: “As social beings, as
creatures who need to be eased out of this world and settled safely into the
next and into memory.”
What are your thoughts on this? Let me know.
See you all tomorrow.
Buh-bye.
Comments
Post a Comment